First-order logic (FOL) proofs build on propositional logic by introducing predicates, quantifiers, and variables. This allows for more complex reasoning about relationships between objects and properties in a given domain.
Constructing FOL proofs involves translating natural language arguments into formal notation, then applying inference rules to derive conclusions. Key strategies include direct proofs, indirect proofs, and goal-oriented approaches like working backwards from the conclusion.
Translating Arguments into FOL Proofs
Key Components of FOL Proofs
- FOL proofs consist of a sequence of well-formed formulas (wffs)
- Each wff is either a premise, an assumption introduced by a subproof, or follows from previous wffs by an inference rule
- Premises are the starting points of the argument, assumptions are temporary statements used in subproofs, and derived statements follow logically from the premises and assumptions
- Translation from natural language to FOL involves identifying the logical structure of the argument
- Identify premises, conclusion, and any hidden assumptions necessary for the argument to be valid
- Break down complex statements into simpler propositions connected by logical operators
- Ensure that the formal representation captures the intended meaning and logical relationships of the natural language argument
Representing Arguments in FOL
- Predicates, constants, and variables must be carefully chosen to accurately represent the entities and relationships described in the natural language argument
- Predicates represent properties or relations (is_red(x), loves(x, y))
- Constants represent specific objects or individuals (alice, bob)
- Variables represent arbitrary objects in the domain of discourse (x, y, z)
- Quantifiers (universal and existential) are used to express the scope of the variables in the argument
- Universal quantifier (โ): asserts that a statement holds for all objects in the domain (โx is_human(x) โ is_mortal(x))
- Existential quantifier (โ): asserts that a statement holds for at least one object in the domain (โx is_prime(x) โง is_even(x))
- Logical connectives (conjunction, disjunction, implication, and negation) are used to capture the logical relationships between the propositions in the argument
- Conjunction (โง): asserts that both propositions are true (is_red(x) โง is_round(x))
- Disjunction (โจ): asserts that at least one of the propositions is true (is_student(x) โจ is_teacher(x))
- Implication (โ): asserts that if the first proposition is true, then the second proposition must also be true (is_human(x) โ is_mortal(x))
- Negation (ยฌ): asserts that a proposition is not true (ยฌis_even(3))
Strategies for Constructing Proofs
Direct and Indirect Proof Strategies
- The direct proof strategy starts with the premises and applies inference rules to derive the conclusion step by step
- Begin with the given premises and assumptions
- Apply inference rules to derive new statements that logically follow from the previous statements
- Continue this process until the conclusion is derived
- The indirect proof strategy assumes the negation of the conclusion and derives a contradiction, thereby proving the original conclusion by reductio ad absurdum
- Assume the negation of the conclusion as a new premise
- Derive a contradiction (a statement that is always false, such as P โง ยฌP) using the premises, assumptions, and inference rules
- Since a contradiction is derived, the assumed negation of the conclusion must be false, implying that the original conclusion is true
Goal-Oriented Strategies
- Working backwards from the conclusion involves considering what premises and inference rules would be needed to derive the conclusion, and then working towards those subgoals
- Identify the conclusion to be proved
- Consider what premises or derived statements could be used to directly infer the conclusion using an inference rule
- Work backwards, identifying the premises or subgoals needed to derive those statements, until the given premises are reached
- Proof by cases considers different possible scenarios and shows that the conclusion holds in each case
- Identify the different cases or scenarios relevant to the argument (P, ยฌP)
- Prove the conclusion holds for each case separately
- Conclude that the conclusion holds in general, since it holds for all possible cases
- Proof by contradiction assumes the negation of the conclusion and derives a contradiction with the premises or known facts
- Assume the negation of the conclusion
- Derive a contradiction using the premises, assumptions, and inference rules
- Conclude that the original conclusion must be true, since its negation leads to a contradiction
Inference Rules and Proof Techniques in FOL
Propositional Inference Rules
- Modus ponens (โ-elimination): If P and PโQ are true, then Q is true
- Example: If "Socrates is a man" (P) and "If Socrates is a man, then Socrates is mortal" (PโQ) are true, then "Socrates is mortal" (Q) is true
- Modus tollens (MT): If PโQ and ยฌQ are true, then ยฌP is true
- Example: If "If it is raining, then the ground is wet" (PโQ) and "The ground is not wet" (ยฌQ) are true, then "It is not raining" (ยฌP) is true
- Hypothetical syllogism (HS): If PโQ and QโR are true, then PโR is true
- Example: If "If I study hard, I will pass the exam" (PโQ) and "If I pass the exam, I will graduate" (QโR) are true, then "If I study hard, I will graduate" (PโR) is true
- Disjunctive syllogism (โจ-elimination): If PโจQ and ยฌP are true, then Q is true
- Example: If "Either the suspect is guilty, or the witness is lying" (PโจQ) and "The suspect is not guilty" (ยฌP) are true, then "The witness is lying" (Q) is true
- Constructive dilemma (CD): If (PโQ)โง(RโS) and PโจR are true, then QโจS is true
- Example: If "If it rains, I will bring an umbrella" (PโQ) and "If it is sunny, I will wear sunglasses" (RโS) are true, and "It is either raining or sunny" (PโจR) is true, then "I will either bring an umbrella or wear sunglasses" (QโจS) is true
Quantifier Inference Rules
- Universal instantiation (UI): If โx P(x) is true, then P(c) is true for any constant c
- Example: If "All humans are mortal" (โx is_human(x) โ is_mortal(x)) is true, then "Socrates is mortal" (is_mortal(socrates)) is true, given that Socrates is a constant representing a human
- Existential generalization (EG): If P(c) is true for some constant c, then โx P(x) is true
- Example: If "Socrates is a philosopher" (is_philosopher(socrates)) is true, then "There exists a philosopher" (โx is_philosopher(x)) is true
- Existential instantiation (EI): If โx P(x) is true, then P(c) is true for some new constant c
- Example: If "There exists a prime number" (โx is_prime(x)) is true, then we can introduce a new constant 'p' and assert "p is a prime number" (is_prime(p))
- Universal generalization (UG): If P(c) is true for an arbitrary constant c, then โx P(x) is true
- Example: If we prove that "For an arbitrary triangle t, the sum of the angles of t is 180 degrees" (sum_of_angles(t) = 180), then we can conclude that "For all triangles, the sum of the angles is 180 degrees" (โx is_triangle(x) โ sum_of_angles(x) = 180)
Variable Instantiation and Quantifier Scope in FOL
Variable Instantiation
- Variables in FOL are used to represent arbitrary objects in the domain of discourse
- Variables are typically represented by lowercase letters (x, y, z)
- Variables do not have a specific referent until they are instantiated with a constant or a specific object
- Universal instantiation allows the substitution of a constant for a universally quantified variable
- If a statement holds for all objects in the domain, then it must hold for any specific object
- Example: From "All humans are mortal" (โx is_human(x) โ is_mortal(x)), we can infer "If Socrates is human, then Socrates is mortal" (is_human(socrates) โ is_mortal(socrates))
- Existential instantiation introduces a new constant to represent an object that satisfies an existentially quantified statement
- If a statement holds for at least one object in the domain, we can introduce a new constant to represent that object and reason about it
- Example: From "There exists a prime number" (โx is_prime(x)), we can introduce a new constant 'p' and assert "p is a prime number" (is_prime(p))
Quantifier Scope
- The scope of a quantifier is the portion of the formula it governs
- The scope of a quantifier determines which variables are bound by the quantifier and which are free
- Example: In the formula โx (P(x) โ โy Q(x, y)), the scope of โx is (P(x) โ โy Q(x, y)), and the scope of โy is Q(x, y)
- Quantifier scope can affect the meaning and validity of a statement
- Example: โx โy P(x, y) is not equivalent to โy โx P(x, y). The first states that for every x, there exists a y such that P(x, y) holds, while the second states that there exists a single y such that for every x, P(x, y) holds
- When instantiating variables, it is crucial to consider the scope of the quantifiers to avoid invalid inferences
- Existential fallacy: Incorrectly assuming that a statement holds for all objects when it only holds for some
- Example: From "Some students are tall" (โx is_student(x) โง is_tall(x)), it is invalid to conclude "All students are tall" (โx is_student(x) โ is_tall(x))
- Illicit universal generalization: Incorrectly generalizing a statement to all objects when it only holds for a specific object
- Example: From "Socrates is a mortal philosopher" (is_philosopher(socrates) โง is_mortal(socrates)), it is invalid to conclude "All philosophers are mortal" (โx is_philosopher(x) โ is_mortal(x))
- Existential fallacy: Incorrectly assuming that a statement holds for all objects when it only holds for some
- Careful management of variable instantiation and quantifier scope is necessary to construct valid FOL proofs and avoid common pitfalls in reasoning
- Ensure that variables are properly instantiated within the scope of their respective quantifiers
- Be cautious when generalizing or instantiating statements to avoid invalid inferences
- Use variable renaming or subscripts to avoid confusion when multiple quantifiers are involved (โx โy P(x, y) vs. โx โy P(x, yโ))